The Grey Man
το φως εν τη σκοτια φαινει
@DoIMustHaveAnUsername? introduced the thought of Wilfrid Sellars to me some time ago and, though I originally rejected his "Myth of the Given"—the notion that our beliefs are not grounded in immediate knowledge given by sensory experience—due to my own foundationalist conviction that beliefs are grounded in experience, I have since become convinced that foundationalism is wrong because knowledge is real and beliefs are not. I know that there is a computer screen in front of me—I do possess immediate knowledge—but to say that I "believe" that it is in front of me is merely to say that I will act as if I know it to be. Immediate knowledge cannot be grounded in beliefs because "beliefs" are merely an immaterial abstract concept that we use to explain our actions in an economical manner.
The same is true, mutatis mutandis, of money. Money has no causal agency and explains nothing; what does explain our actions in relation to concrete objects that are said to "represent" money, such as coins and notes, is our knowledge of the past practical consequences of failing to conform to certain socially-enforced rules regarding their handling, which serves as a motive not to, for example, overtly cheat other people.
(@Hadoblado, you can add my conversion to epistemological anti-foundationalism to your list of times that someone on this forum has been convinced to adopt a position contrary to their previous belief.)
This is related to another merit of Sellars' thought: his discovery that we theorize about our own thoughts in terms invented to describe public objects, and not the other way around. The good part of Sellars' epistemology, then, consists in his criticism of foundationalism combined with his inversion of the Cartesian paradigm whereby our theories about external objects are understood to be extensions of our theories about our own thoughts.
The bad part, I think, is that he thought that not just our theories of our own thoughts, but also our theories of our own sensations, were derived from our theories about public objects. I myself recognize no division between sensations and public objects at all; rather, I think a public object is merely a sensation shared by two or more people. I believe the world of subjective sensation and the world of objective perception to be co-extensive, two aspects of the same private, "windowless" experience. Where there is correspondence between features of two or more experiences, there is publicity.
The ugly part is that, like most of the "analytic" or "positivist" philosophers of the 20th century, who thought that the purpose of philosophy (love of wisdom) was merely to clarify scientific theories and reconcile them with intuitive experience (despite my admiration for G.E. Moore, he, too, belongs to this class), he doesn't seem to have said anything of any practical importance to anyone, for all of his prodigious systematizing. Oh, well. At least he wasn't a Hegelian.
The same is true, mutatis mutandis, of money. Money has no causal agency and explains nothing; what does explain our actions in relation to concrete objects that are said to "represent" money, such as coins and notes, is our knowledge of the past practical consequences of failing to conform to certain socially-enforced rules regarding their handling, which serves as a motive not to, for example, overtly cheat other people.
(@Hadoblado, you can add my conversion to epistemological anti-foundationalism to your list of times that someone on this forum has been convinced to adopt a position contrary to their previous belief.)
This is related to another merit of Sellars' thought: his discovery that we theorize about our own thoughts in terms invented to describe public objects, and not the other way around. The good part of Sellars' epistemology, then, consists in his criticism of foundationalism combined with his inversion of the Cartesian paradigm whereby our theories about external objects are understood to be extensions of our theories about our own thoughts.
The bad part, I think, is that he thought that not just our theories of our own thoughts, but also our theories of our own sensations, were derived from our theories about public objects. I myself recognize no division between sensations and public objects at all; rather, I think a public object is merely a sensation shared by two or more people. I believe the world of subjective sensation and the world of objective perception to be co-extensive, two aspects of the same private, "windowless" experience. Where there is correspondence between features of two or more experiences, there is publicity.
The ugly part is that, like most of the "analytic" or "positivist" philosophers of the 20th century, who thought that the purpose of philosophy (love of wisdom) was merely to clarify scientific theories and reconcile them with intuitive experience (despite my admiration for G.E. Moore, he, too, belongs to this class), he doesn't seem to have said anything of any practical importance to anyone, for all of his prodigious systematizing. Oh, well. At least he wasn't a Hegelian.