The Grey Man
το φως εν τη σκοτια φαινει
What follows is crude. Its purpose is to stimulate discourse and to respond to some posts made in the “Awaiting Orders” thread and in other places.
Consider that central identity of Schopenhauer which has been shamelessly appropriated by his present-day coattail riders David Chalmers and Giulio Tononi: that between the Cartesian simple subject (“I”) and an act of will, between the phenomenological and the causal properties of experience, between perception and appétition, which in Leibniz’s Monadologie are adamantly separate elements of consciousness.
Consider also, reciprocally, that other identity of Schopenhauer which Chalmers and Tononi have not adopted, but which is the complement of the first in forming a complete image of the world: namely, that between what is known indirectly as the changes undergone by the organic spatial relations that thoroughly characterize the manifoldness of objects in space (that complex which Tononi calls “integrated information” and which Leibniz calls the “multitude dans l’unité”) comprehended by the subject in a transient act of cognition- the passage of time in Kant’s transcendental unity of apperception- and what is known directly as the penetration of this cognitive space by a temporal willing. In other words, the second is an identity between what is seen extensively as a transcendent causal order, as the patterns manifest in the changes undergone by mutually individuated entities (māyā: the matter of natural philosophy, which is the expression of a universal through particulars, the revelation of a truth which is a sum of facts) and what is felt immanently and intensively as willing (duḥkha: the matter of art, which is the expression of universals through a particular, the revelation through facts of a truth by and through their more or less immediate- less or more physiognomic- stimulation of affect), that immensely revelatory element of experience which contemporary philosophers of the mind have all but ignored to flatter their misguided sense of objectivity and which, at its most intense, we call passion and suffering.
The first identity starts with the subject and moves to the object (ex uno plures) whereas the second starts with the object and moves to the subject (e pluribus unum), however both express the same thought: that consciousness is fundamentally a union of opposites, of willing (time) and idea (space). The latter stands to the former much as does an invisible vessel whose form is revealed only when it is filled with opaque matter (to paraphrase Hamlet, “nothing is either good or bad or red or green, but thinking makes it so”*).
Meanwhile, the temporal-willful aspect of the “I” stands to the spatial-phenomenal as do the tensions in a length of thread to the shape it assumes as it is woven into a tapestry. The tensions tell us how the thread has been stretched and squeezed to accommodate its neighbours and vice versa, and this gives us an inkling of how its neighbours may in turn have been stretched, squeezed, and made tense to accommodate it, but this does not tell us how, on the whole, they have been made tense, nor indeed that the whole tapestry is not one endless strand and that when we speak of one thread and its neighbours straining against themselves to form an interdependent lattice (δίκη ἔρις- strife is justice; to Goethe, this is the compensatory opposition between the drive to formation, the Bildungstrieb in the microcosm and in the macrocosm), we are not speaking of a single thread which is both immanent and transcendent in all.
From Wikipedia:
The tapestry is the thing in itself, that which can only be comprehended negatively and thus intelligibly as that which is not the “I”. In our view it remains the same mysterium tremendum, the same unspeakable noumenon that it was to Kant. Every act disappears into the unfathomable abyss of our ignorance, its full transcendent significance never to be revealed.
It is this profound limit on human knowledge that permitted Leibniz to postulate an ungainly separation between perception and appetition that has constantly to be mediated by a micro-managing God. It is also what permits pompous utilitarians to champion grand political endeavours dedicated to the illustrious tradition of craven slave morality predicated upon the ludicrous claim that that the minds of humans and some animals are alone the heirs to suffering even though the objective corollary of suffering- causation- is present everywhere else in nature. Leibniz’s mill argument, to my mind, placed the onus decisively on them to justify their archaic dualistic nonsense some 300 years ago, not that I expect dull ideologues to condescend to questions of philosophy, regardless of how morally relevant they are to their foolish projects. Anyway, if I’m not mistaken, we stand with Schopenhauer at the summit of Western philosophy, for no doctrine before or since has provided so elegant and comprehensive a solution to the “riddle of existence”, as he called it, excepting those of such rare giants as Gautama and Heraclitus, with whose thought his converged. And in philosophy, parsimony, and no assurance of being right, is the best result one can hope for.
Thoughts? I would like to be told I'm wrong. Convincingly.
Consider that central identity of Schopenhauer which has been shamelessly appropriated by his present-day coattail riders David Chalmers and Giulio Tononi: that between the Cartesian simple subject (“I”) and an act of will, between the phenomenological and the causal properties of experience, between perception and appétition, which in Leibniz’s Monadologie are adamantly separate elements of consciousness.
Consider also, reciprocally, that other identity of Schopenhauer which Chalmers and Tononi have not adopted, but which is the complement of the first in forming a complete image of the world: namely, that between what is known indirectly as the changes undergone by the organic spatial relations that thoroughly characterize the manifoldness of objects in space (that complex which Tononi calls “integrated information” and which Leibniz calls the “multitude dans l’unité”) comprehended by the subject in a transient act of cognition- the passage of time in Kant’s transcendental unity of apperception- and what is known directly as the penetration of this cognitive space by a temporal willing. In other words, the second is an identity between what is seen extensively as a transcendent causal order, as the patterns manifest in the changes undergone by mutually individuated entities (māyā: the matter of natural philosophy, which is the expression of a universal through particulars, the revelation of a truth which is a sum of facts) and what is felt immanently and intensively as willing (duḥkha: the matter of art, which is the expression of universals through a particular, the revelation through facts of a truth by and through their more or less immediate- less or more physiognomic- stimulation of affect), that immensely revelatory element of experience which contemporary philosophers of the mind have all but ignored to flatter their misguided sense of objectivity and which, at its most intense, we call passion and suffering.
The first identity starts with the subject and moves to the object (ex uno plures) whereas the second starts with the object and moves to the subject (e pluribus unum), however both express the same thought: that consciousness is fundamentally a union of opposites, of willing (time) and idea (space). The latter stands to the former much as does an invisible vessel whose form is revealed only when it is filled with opaque matter (to paraphrase Hamlet, “nothing is either good or bad or red or green, but thinking makes it so”*).
* To make the inflection from the phenomenological to the causal meaning of this, the difference between seeing red and seeing green is the difference between transmitting a digit in a binary message as aught and as naught, which is to say that there is no difference except that in the effects upon the receivers of the message, what messages result from these, and so on. To paraphrase Marshall McLuhan, “The medium is the incoming message is the medium is the outgoing message is the medium is the incoming...ad infinitum.” In other words, qualia are ineffable except insofar as their relations with other qualia can be elucidated because they are nothing more than these relations, and these relations, as a whole, nothing more than the full characterization of the objective complex as patient and, reciprocally, of the simple subject as agent. πάντα ῥεῖ- everything flows.
Meanwhile, the temporal-willful aspect of the “I” stands to the spatial-phenomenal as do the tensions in a length of thread to the shape it assumes as it is woven into a tapestry. The tensions tell us how the thread has been stretched and squeezed to accommodate its neighbours and vice versa, and this gives us an inkling of how its neighbours may in turn have been stretched, squeezed, and made tense to accommodate it, but this does not tell us how, on the whole, they have been made tense, nor indeed that the whole tapestry is not one endless strand and that when we speak of one thread and its neighbours straining against themselves to form an interdependent lattice (δίκη ἔρις- strife is justice; to Goethe, this is the compensatory opposition between the drive to formation, the Bildungstrieb in the microcosm and in the macrocosm), we are not speaking of a single thread which is both immanent and transcendent in all.
From Wikipedia:
The Druze (/druːz/; Arabic: درزي darzī or durzī, plural دروز durūz; Hebrew: דרוזי drūzī plural דרוזים, druzim) are an Arabic-speaking esoteric ethnoreligious group originating in Western Asia who self-identify as unitarians (Al-Muwaḥḥidūn/Muwahhidun). Jethro of Midian is considered an ancestor of all people from the Mountain of Druze region, who revere him as their spiritual founder and chief prophet.
...
The main Druze doctrine states that God is both transcendent and immanent, in which he is above all attributes but at the same time he is present.
In their desire to maintain a rigid confession of unity, they stripped from God all attributes (tanzīh). In God, there are no attributes distinct from his essence. He is wise, mighty, and just, not by wisdom, might and justice, but by his own essence. God is "the whole of existence", rather than "above existence" or on his throne, which would make him "limited". There is neither "how", "when", nor "where" about him; he is incomprehensible.
The tapestry is the thing in itself, that which can only be comprehended negatively and thus intelligibly as that which is not the “I”. In our view it remains the same mysterium tremendum, the same unspeakable noumenon that it was to Kant. Every act disappears into the unfathomable abyss of our ignorance, its full transcendent significance never to be revealed.
Cartoon Jethro said:A single thread in a tapestry,
though its colour brightly shines,
can never see its purpose,
in the pattern of the grand design.
It is this profound limit on human knowledge that permitted Leibniz to postulate an ungainly separation between perception and appetition that has constantly to be mediated by a micro-managing God. It is also what permits pompous utilitarians to champion grand political endeavours dedicated to the illustrious tradition of craven slave morality predicated upon the ludicrous claim that that the minds of humans and some animals are alone the heirs to suffering even though the objective corollary of suffering- causation- is present everywhere else in nature. Leibniz’s mill argument, to my mind, placed the onus decisively on them to justify their archaic dualistic nonsense some 300 years ago, not that I expect dull ideologues to condescend to questions of philosophy, regardless of how morally relevant they are to their foolish projects. Anyway, if I’m not mistaken, we stand with Schopenhauer at the summit of Western philosophy, for no doctrine before or since has provided so elegant and comprehensive a solution to the “riddle of existence”, as he called it, excepting those of such rare giants as Gautama and Heraclitus, with whose thought his converged. And in philosophy, parsimony, and no assurance of being right, is the best result one can hope for.
Thoughts? I would like to be told I'm wrong. Convincingly.