The Grey Man
το φως εν τη σκοτια φαινει
Plato said:The truth is this: none of the gods loves wisdom or desires to become wise for they are wise already. Nor does anyone else who is wise love wisdom. Neither do the ignorant love wisdom, or desire to become wise, for this is the harshest thing about ignorance, that those who are neither good nor beautiful nor sensible think that they are good enough. No one desires what they are lacking when they do not think themselves lacking.
Plato's theory of forms, in its various forms, has been one of the most, if not the most persistent school of metaphysical thought in the history of Western civilization. Ever since its systematization and synthesis with nascent Christianity by the Church Fathers in the early centuries of our era, it has been a mainstay of the conceptual arsenal of theologians and theistic apologists of all stripes. The notion that this visible, temporal world of Becoming in which we all live is a distorted representation of an occult, changeless world of Being has ever served as a means of theoretically reconciling the multiplicity and corruptibility of concrete things with the eternal, undivided goodness of God. With the rise of empiricist metaphysics in the wake of the scientific revolution inaugurated by Copernicus, Galileo, Bacon, and, above all, Newton, we may now ask, What residual relevance does the old Platonic way of thinking about the world retain, if any? With this new emphasis on the observable and the testable, is there any room for thinking about things as they are independently of human experience?
The answer to this question will, I think, become clear to anyone who understands just what Plato is talking about when he talks about "forms." In one of his dialogues, he has Socrates explain them rather poetically to the aristocrat Meno as the features (perhaps the hills and clouds) of a world of truth that his soul used to inhabit before she took up residence in this false one. According to Socrates, the soul has forgotten about this prenatal world, but can "recollect" certain features of it by recognizing in the particular objects of everyday life certain universal forms. Now, it is common to pay lip service to Plato, to say that, though his theory of forms was a spirited "early attempt" at acquiring knowledge, he could provide only the semblance of a solution using metaphorical language because he lacked the sophisticated hypothetico-deductive method that modern scientists use to produce meaningful statements about the world. This narrative, however, ignores the fact that Plato's forms are not theoretical posits the causal agency of which is a hypothesis to be experimentally tested. They are not the cause of any specific natural phenomenon, but the conditions of the representation of phenomena in general. It was not for no reason that the sign above the entrance to the Academy read: "Let no-one ignorant of geometry enter here."
Indeed, Socrates illustrates his notion of "recollection" by showing that one of Meno's slaves, who lacks any knowledge of geometrical concepts, is nevertheless capable of perceiving geometrical necessities. Socrates draws a hollow square on the ground and asks the slave how the size of the area on the inside of the square can be doubled. The slave betrays his ignorance by guessing that the lengths of the sides must be doubled but, when Socrates extends the sides to be equal to the diagonal distance between any two opposite corners of the square, the slave immediately agrees that this is the correct procedure, not just for the square in front of him, but for all squares—and herein lies the difference between scientific knowledge and mathematical knowledge. We can easily imagine the discontinuation of any apparently exceptionless dynamical pattern (e.g. the failure of the sun to rise tomorrow morning), but we cannot imagine any breach of mathematical law. Hence why so many scientists are empiricist thinkers and so many mathematicians Platonists.
This is all well and good, but if Socratic recollection is going to be of practical use to us, we must be able to "remember" not only mathematical laws, but moral ones as well. We must somehow already know what is good without knowing that we know it; we must be ignorant in our wisdom and wise in our ignorance.* What do you think? Are we in possession of ethical knowledge without knowing it? Is Socratic philosophy possible?
*
Samuel Johnson said:Love is the wisdom of the fool and the folly of the wise.
Rumi said:Love is the astrolabe of God's mysteries.
Could it be...?